Thursday, November 17, 2011

Democracy & Equality



Many theorists of democracy think that there is an important connection between some ideal of equality and the desirability of democracy. Explain and discuss this connection. Do you think it is sufficient to justify democratic institutions?

This paper shows why both democracy and equality are desirable, and why democracy, in its true sense, is an important step to achieve greater equality. There are many reasons why political philosophers need to look beyond the ‘one person, one vote’ conception of democracy to understand why such theories have allowed social and economic inequality to prevail. While many democracies do not live up to our expectations in regards to providing equality, there are explanations for this and methods of overcoming such problems.

Is equality desirable?
The first thing to consider is whether equality is desirable, and if so, what kinds of equality are desirable. For example, should young children have equal voting rights with adult persons? The consensus around this issue in most democracies is that there is an age where children should not be able to vote (even if there is disagreement on exactly what the age should be). However, it does not follow that it is permissible for children to be discriminated against by the law because they are unable to vote. For example, if an election is held when Bob is 17 and 11 months, and James has just turned 18, James is by no means worth more than Bob. James may in fact know a lot less about politics than Bob. An individual can be excluded from the demos yet still have equal value as a person. Therefore, the crucial issue is that there is that in similar circumstances, different people are treated equally. To determine whether equality is, in the first instance, desirable we must consider what is meant by the term ‘equality.’
Equality is often considered to be important exclusively within a designated demos. This is important because it facilitates an ongoing conversation and reflection on individual preferences. The laws created by the demos are seen as binding upon them. This is partially where our obligation to follow the laws of the government arises – because we voted them in and are bound by the social contract. Of course, there will always be questions of legitimacy and what obliges the disenfranchised minority to follow the laws of the majority. However, when there has been some effective compromise and deliberation which has influenced the outcome, there seems to be a morally binding obligation to follow the law.[1]
Consider the case of the recently proposed Malaysia solution. The proposed deal between Malaysia and Australia would have meant that 800 asylum seekers who travel to Australia by boat would be sent to Malaysia in order to deter others, while Australia, in exchange would take 4000 refugees from one of Malaysia’s refugee camps. The intended effect was to ‘stop the boats’ and save the Australian government from political turmoil. The people who this legislation has the greatest effect on are the asylum seekers who plan to travel to Australia by boat, and the asylum seekers who are waiting in refugee camps in Malaysia. However, because these groups of people are not part of the demos creating the law, and have no influence on the legislation, are they obliged to follow it? While the interests of those seeking asylum in Australia should be considered by the demos in a democracy, this does not give anyone who interacts with the state the automatic right to the ballot and citizenship. In summary, there is a type of equality which each person has, but it does not always follow that every person in the world is entitled to have citizenship of a nation-state in order for the state to acknowledge the equality of persons. It may seem arbitrary to argue that a demos is constituted by a particular geographical location, but this is not the case. It is in fact quite pragmatic, as the geographical relationship between each member of a nation-state helps form the nation’s life.
Myers points out that there are ‘virtually limitless ways in which human beings might be equal or unequal.’[2] From birth, individuals develop and pursue different talents and strengths, yet their individual uniqueness does not render them unequal. Some individual differences, like illness or disability will, however, mean that the individuals concerned are on unequal footing to pursue their respective interests. If one was to divide the medication belonging to a sick person into portions so that the healthy person receives some of the medication too, they would not be pursuing equality. Ensuring that both the sick and healthy do not have access to medical supplies is to not act equally. Equality demands different responses to unequal situations.

The principle of equal consideration
The principle of equal consideration is sometimes thought to be compatible with democracy. This principle, attributed to Jeremy Bentham, suggests that ‘everyone must count for one and no more than one.’[3] In a procedural sense, this is true of most liberal democracies. Everyone has equal rights to vote, free speech, freedom of assembly, and so on. While procedural equality grants each person rights to be able to express their political views in various manners, these rights are not obligations. Therefore, government responsiveness to each citizen will not be equal, as some citizens participate more than others. Is this an issue for democracy? It is arguable that this is not an issue because each person still has equality of opportunity; it seems that they can each participate if they choose to. However, there are other factors in play. As Green notes, there is a class of people who write to their representatives and receive an impersonal response. Their opinions have been ‘hopelessly devalued’. On the other hand, there is another class of people who will be consulted without request.[4] This seems to be straying away from Bentham’s suggestion that each person only count for one, and for no more than one.
Although there is a sense of procedural equality in many liberal democracies, correlative substantive equality among individual citizens does not always follow. There is nothing intrinsically wrong with citizens participating different amounts, this is surely inevitable in any conceivable construction of society.  The point of concern is why participation levels differ. Verba and Nie suggest that participation levels differ because ‘motivation, skills, [and] resources are not equally distributed.’ According to their empirical study, the authors found that upper-status citizens are six times more likely to be in the category of ‘highest participant’ than citizens from low socioeconomic backgrounds.  The study concludes that this leads to an ‘unequal distribution of participation.’[5]
Brighouse asks the reader: ‘Why should it matter if Julian, who has boundless enthusiasm for participation in public life , wields more influence than Sandy, who prefers to hone his psychic talents?’[6] The author suggests that this is perfectly compatible with what he coins the ‘equal availability of political influence’. While it is tempting to agree with Brighouse from the outset, there are reasons as to why we should be cautious. Every inequality of political influence is not reconcilable, and every element of substantive equality is not achievable from political equality (nor is it necessarily desirable). However, there is a strong case to reduce political inequalities and substantive inequalities in order to attain a society where one really does count for one. Therefore, if Sandy chooses not to participate in the political process our concern is not with forcing him to increase his participation so that he may realise equality, but rather, our concern regards to whether there are other external factors that have caused him to be less involved and caused Julian to have a greater involvement. For example, if Sandy had never learnt in school that he was able to run for political office, this would concern the advocate of equality. If he had ingrained into him from a young age, the belief that people of his race, class, area, or intelligence were unable to cause any significant change through political institutions, this would concern the proponent of equality. Therefore, while Sandy and Julian both have equal opportunity to participate in the procedural system, the political philosopher must look beyond this assertion to ask why various groups are less inclined to practice their democratic rights.

Qualitative and normative equality
Christiano proposes a solution to the problem of the procedural equality paradox by valuing qualitative equality over normative equality. Qualitative equality has a greater focus on supply, while normative equality has a greater focus on demand. If we are to only focus on demand, then the views of the minority will be given less consideration. The principle of equal consideration suggests that each person, Mary, John, and Jane, should have an equal say. However, the concept of substantive equality proposes that if Mary and John both support idea A, while Jane supports idea B, there should not necessarily be twice as many resources put into idea A. If Mary has put forward her view, John does not need to put forward the same argument again, whereas, it is important that Jane puts forth her  view. Christiano suggests that in discourse we can learn a lot from hearing the views of others, and therefore, we should focus on the fact that there is supply of both idea A and B, and not on the fact that there is greater demand for idea A.[7] Focussing on qualitative equality in discourse is one step to addressing the inequalities created by the varying participation levels of groups with diverse ideas. However, it prescribes nothing on how one ought to decide.

Philosophical problems with the current situation
The following section will focus on how procedural equality is adversely hampered by substantive inequality. The first issue to be tackled is the problem of political elites. Green notes that those making decisions for the vast majority of society don’t actually represent their constituents. He writes that ‘transportation policies are made by people who fly in (subsidised) private planes, are driven by chauffeurs, and generally travel first class in every way possible.’[8] In addition to this, it is visible in Australia that those making laws on refugee policies have never been refugees, those making decisions on climate change are not the poor who are most reliant on the land, and those who decide how much money goes to public housing have never been homeless. Political elites are ‘of a different effective social class from the bulk of their constituents.’[9]
Is this a bad thing for democracy and equality? Surely there is some expectation that those who are elected to the highest offices have expert skills, enabling them to make considered decisions? It is possible to have equality without democracy, and perhaps complete equality is more compatible with benevolent dictatorship. However, as was pointed out previously in this paper, the people have less of an obligation to follow laws that they did not help make. Often, dictatorships are not benevolent, or only benevolent to few, so it appears to be rather utopian to suggest that a functioning liberal democracy will not be the best form of government to implement equality. Therefore, proper representation through electing leaders who do not just represent the peoples’ views but also represent the peoples’ material status is important. To grasp a solution to this problem, the political philosopher must ask why the public elect people who are of a different social class to their constituents.
As noted earlier by Verba and Nie, there is not an equal distribution of participation among voters, and this can be broken up into social class. The rich are typically able to exercise greater influence over politics and how society is constructed as compared to the poor. Brighouse gives some clear reasons for why this is the case: ‘they (the rich) usually have more access to mass media, a more suitable educational background and more leisure time to develop considered views about political issues.’[10] Therefore, the rich typically have a greater ability to persuade others to their views. Christiano suggests that deliberation among equals is one of the most effective ways to gain democratic equality.[11] However, with the rich having better access to education, media, and other resources, it does not seem that deliberation among equals is currently occurring.

Examples of procedural and substantive issues
Over the past few months the world has seen unusually large numbers of people rising up, arguing that there is too much socioeconomic inequality, and furthermore, that money is infiltrating democracy leaving the big decisions in the hands of wealthy corporations. There is not merely a problem in theory with wealth and democracy, but as we shall see, it is a very serious problem in practice for democratic nation-states, now more than ever. The proposed mining super-profits tax is an example of where an advertising campaign by wealthy corporations was able to sway public opinion, arguably in a manner which was unhealthy for democracy.[12] In regard to the tax, The Australian provocatively asked the reader ‘How much does it cost to bring down a prime minister? The answer a tad over $22 million.’[13] It seems that the effect of the advertising was what Brighouse described as ‘subliminal manipulation that bypassed the rational capacities of the voter.’[14] He distinguishes this from coming to a decision ‘through a process of ratiocination in conditions of free and equal debate.’[15] While there were multiple factors at play in the ousting of Rudd and the dilution of the super-profits tax, it seems that in this instance, as predicted, the rich won.
Currently, the issue of how to best to tackle problem gambling is receiving attention in the Australian media after Independent Member Andrew Wilkie and Independent Senator Nick Xenophon proposed tougher regulation and limits on how much people can bet. Tim Costello, chairman of the Australian Churches Gambling Taskforce, argues that the $11.8 billion industry is in dire need of reform.[16] With four in every ten dollars coming from problem gamblers, it is understandable as to why change is unattractive to the industry. And while the industry have every right, as equals, to voice their concern, their voice should not be a roar which masks the possibility for progress. Unfortunately, this has been the case. Costello writes that Clubs NSW used ‘political donations to buy government access’ and that Clubs Australia has ‘mounted a sustained campaign of personal attacks’ against the politicians who suggested reform to current pokies legislation.[17] Similar to the campaign by the mining industry against Rudd’s proposed super-profits tax, Clubs Australia will do what they need to do to ensure that their shareholders are satisfied. As often happens when money enters into politics, this leads to an ‘ends justify the means’ scenario. Few of the most virtuous men or women can survive sustained, belligerent, personal attacks of an expensive marketing campaign. This is particularly harmful to democracy.
In summary, democracy is a good way of ensuring a basic standard of equality. However, as shown throughout this paper, there are different levels of democracy. The case studies above have shown that for true democracy to exist, and for correlative equality to come about, the government must ensure that the rich are not drowning out the poor and the working-class. An effective way of bringing this about is by ensuring that equality is a major focus of democratic institutions. This essay supports Myer’s proposition, that ‘government intervention in the economic realm is necessary for the promotion of equal freedom.’[18] True procedural equality cannot be achieved until the substantive problems adversely affecting it are fixed. Once these problems are fixed through better regulation and a higher priority on the supply of ideas rather than just demand, only then will we see the flow on effects from procedural equality.


Bibliography





[1] Singer, Democracy and disobedience, Oxford, 1973, p. 43.
[2] Myers, The politics of equality : an introduction, London; New York; New York, 2010, p. 34.
[3] Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Jeremy Bentham, 2011.
[4] Green, Retrieving democracy : in search of civic equality, Totowa, N.J., 1985, p. 172.
[5] Verba and Nie, Participation in America: political democracy and social equality, New York, 1972, pp. 336-337.
[6] Brighouse, Egalitarianism and Equal Availability of Political Influence, 1996, p. 126.
[7] Christiano, Deliberative Equality and Democratic Order, New York, 1996, pp. 258-259.
[8] Green, Retrieving democracy : in search of civic equality, 1985, p. 177.
[9] Ibid., p. 178.
[10] Brighouse, Egalitarianism and Equal Availability of Political Influence, 1996, p. 120.
[11] Christiano, Deliberative Equality and Democratic Order, 1996, p. 252.
[12] Megalogenis, Trivial Pursuit: Leadership and the End of the Reform Era, 2010, p. 4.
[13] Davis, A snip at $22m to get rid of PM, 2011.
[14] Brighouse, Egalitarianism and Equal Availability of Political Influence, 1996, p. 126.
[15] Ibid., p. 126.
[16] Costello, Clubs use tricky numbers to outfox pokies reform, Sydney, 2011.
[17] Ibid.
[18] Myers, The politics of equality : an introduction, 2010, p. 83.

No comments:

Post a Comment