Apology, forgiveness, and reconciliation will be discussed in this essay Picture from http://goo.gl/k1dbm |
I found this to be a very interesting essay to write. I have considered what forgiveness could mean in a secular democratic environment. However, I'm not sure whether a secular democratic environment is actually the best for society, so I'm not completely sure whether I agree with my conclusion. I think forgiveness could be less limited than I have defined it throughout this essay, however, this is as far as I can justify it through words. This paper was submitted for the subject 'Politics, Violence and Memory'.
Political forgiveness
is limited and problematic, but with appropriate reflection, it can become a
valuable mechanism for reconciliation and transition. I will argue that there
is such thing as political forgiveness, and I will define the term in its many
elements throughout the discussion. In this paper, I seek to validate the
following seven claims: (i) that a commitment to the elimination of resentment
is a necessary, although not sufficient, condition of forgiveness, (ii) the
elimination of resentment therefore does not constitute as forgiveness, (iii)
forgiveness may also require truth, respect, and an openness to reconciliation,
(iv) forgiveness in isolation is not a virtuous characteristic of the citizen
or state, (v) genuine forgiveness is not condonation, nor need it be pardon, (vi)
it is not a victim’s duty to forgive, although it could be regarded as morally
commendable, and (vii) that those who have inherited fortunes from the immoral
actions committed by previous generations could be eligible for forgiveness due
to the injury of illegitimate inheritance.
The concept of
resentment appears regularly in the literature surrounding political forgiveness.
The Oxford English Dictionary describes resentment as a ‘sense of grievance, an
indignant sense of injury or insult received or perceived; (a feeling of) ill
will, bitterness, or anger against a person or thing.’[1] For
forgiveness to be relevant to a situation, one party must have injured another
party. Often in such situations, the injured party will carry some kind of
resentment or ‘ill will’ against the other party. Digeser has suggested that
‘forgiveness requires either the actual elimination of resentment or a
commitment to the process of eliminating it.’[2] A great
deal of my analysis will centre around this assertion.
In relation to
political communities it is crucial to understand whether the only way to move
beyond resentment is through an act of forgiveness, or whether there are means
other than forgiveness that one could use to move beyond resentment. The second
question is whether the elimination of resentment constitutes as forgiveness. I
will contend in regard to the former point that forgiveness generally is a
necessary, although not an entirely sufficient, condition of moving beyond
resentment. In regards to the second question, I will contend that the
elimination of resentment does not constitute as forgiveness.
Some authors such as Nir
Eisikovits have argued that victims can ‘simply move on’ without being
forgiving or resentful.[3] It is
possible that the victim has had some form of memory loss, or fails to
recognise the harm for what it is. However, it seems that in ordinary circumstances
forgiveness from the victim is required for the victim to move beyond her
resentment towards the perpetrator. The very act of abstaining from forgiveness
feeds resentment.[4]
One may ask an injured party, ‘so you still haven’t forgiven him for what he
did to you?’, the injured party may respond by saying ‘no, I chose not to’,
which implies that there is still resentment attached to the injury. If the
injured party responds by saying ‘I saw no need to forgive him,’ the injured
party must not consider the injury to be grave enough to warrant forgiveness.
Only in the circumstance where the injured party does not fully recognise the
extent of his injury (or in fact the injury was minimal in the first instance)
could the injured party adequately move on without harbouring feelings of
resentment in circumstances where the injured party chooses not to or is unable
to offer forgiveness to her perpetrator.
In regard to the
second point, it is possible for the elimination of resentment to be a
necessary condition of forgiveness without the elimination of resentment being
forgiveness in itself. For a victim to forgive his perpetrator, the victim must
experience more than a lack of resentment. While committing to the elimination
of resentment may be the first and most challenging condition of forgiveness,
it does not appear to be adequately sufficient. Forgiveness may also require truth,
respect, and an openness to reconciliation in addition to a commitment to the
elimination of resentment.
Forgiveness has been
described as a virtue of the saintly. While this may be the case in the private
realm, the virtuous nature of forgiveness in the public-political realm is
ambiguous. Downie suggests that ‘readiness to forgive is a virtue and inability
to forgive, or at least unwillingness to try, a vice.’[5] However,
it is also clear that being too quick to offer forgiveness ‘may result in the
weakening of moral restraints on other people’s immoral conduct.’[6]
Therefore, it is difficult to find the balance between embodying some kind of ‘forgiving
spirit’ while not supporting an immoral act. This point, is particularly
relevant to political forgiveness as the perception from the public that a
state is condoning an act behind the masquerade of ‘political forgiveness’ is
more than plausible, and may have a negative rather than positive effect on the
overall situation. More often though, the state is the party who has either
been active or complicit in a mass atrocity; the state is the party that is
asking for forgiveness. This raises issues with accountability, especially in a
political environment that is democratic. Hastily forgiving the wrongs committed
by an elected political representative, if widely embraced, could potentially radically
undermine the principles of democracy and citizenship as we know them. I will
elaborate on this in the last part of the discussion. It will suffice for now
to suggest that of the political virtues that have been expounded upon by
thinkers such as John Rawls, John Locke, and Immanuel Kant, it would seem that
forgiveness is not one of them, or perhaps more precisely, it is not on its own
sufficient. Virtues such as respect, equality, dignity, and accountability have
historically had a much stronger connection to political life.
It would be
reasonable to suggest that if by the very nature of granting forgiveness one
must also simultaneously grant pardon and condone the act of injury,
forgiveness would have little, if no political appeal. Downie suggests that
there are two main reasons why forgiveness and condonation have become
confused. The first is in relation to the trivial definition of forgiveness, as
in, ‘forgive me for interrupting your meal’, which is more similar to a soft
apology which would not in normal circumstances require acceptance from the
other party as there was no injury caused. This kind of forgiveness has more to
do with courtesy and common language usage, which has little relevance with
political forgiveness that may be requested or offered in the aftermath of a mass atrocity. The second confusion relates
specifically to condonation, ‘that condonation is frequently used as a morally
inferior substitute for forgiving.’[7] The
point which Downie is trying to draw out here is that there are often times
when people ‘forgive’ an immoral practice because it is in their self-interest.
It is, in the cruel sense of the term, in my self-interest to ‘forgive’
companies that use slave-made cocoa, blood diamonds, or natural rainforest materials.
I am tempted to ‘forgive’ my government for her involvement in wars, the
ill-treatment of asylum seekers, or the pollution of the environment because it
is in my self-interest to make myself believe that I am kind-heartedly
‘forgiving’ these practices when I am in fact condoning them. In summary, the
kind of forgiveness that is synonymous with condonation of an immoral act
is not the kind of forgiveness which is being explored in this paper.
Forgiveness is the condonation of the person behind the act while
simultaneously being the condemnation of the act itself.[8] Unless
the act and the person can be separated, it is unlikely that the victim will be
able to forgive her offender.
Forgiveness in some
cases may mean that pardon is granted, however, this is by no means a rule. If
a person genuinely desires forgiveness she should still accept her dues. The
victim or a judge who has authority over the matter may decide to lessen the
punishment because of the perpetrator’s repentance. However, it is out of
generosity that a level of pardon may be granted to the perpetrator. The
perpetrator still ought to receive her just deserts, provided that they are not
motivated by the victim’s sense of resentment. Downie suggests that ‘to pardon
is in fact to condone’, or in other words, if to forgive is not to condone, and
to pardon is to condone, then to forgive is not to pardon.[9] In some
circumstances, especially in regard to personal acts of forgiveness, the victim
has the liberty to pardon the offender. In regard to political forgiveness to
pardon entirely is effectively to condone. However, the choices need not be
between pardon and retribution. Reparations, compensation, and restitution are
just a few examples of alternatives to retribution which would, all things
being equal, not condone or pardon an immoral action. The distinct yet related
concepts of forgiveness, pardon, and condonation should not be confused with
one another.
Genuine forgiveness
must flow from generosity rather than obligation. It may be morally commendable
for a person to forgive her offender, but it could never be a moral obligation.
The terms ‘charity’ and ‘duty’ have often been viewed as synonymous, however,
this is an error in need of clarification. Duty relates to the debt that is
owed, for example, the debt that the offender owes to the victim. As Marina
suggests in her exposition on Kant, ‘if we have a moral claim on someone’s
doing something, then for the person to grant what is due to us, it is to act
justly, not graciously.’[10] If an
offender compensates their victim, they do not do so out of ‘charity’ or from a
kind heart (although the offender may happen to be a ‘charitable’ or
‘kind-hearted’ person), this is an act of justice. Forgiveness is not a duty or
an act of equalising justice, but rather, it is an act similar to charity which
could be viewed as morally commendable.
Lastly, I want to
touch on the issue of identity. Forgiveness, apology, and reconciliation becomes
more complex in the political realm, as the political realm has to deal with
individuals, groups, and generations which have dynamic identities. This
complexity was most recently brought under the spotlight in regard the apology
by the Australian Government for the ill-treatment of Indigenous Australians. Former
Prime Minister of Australia, John Howard, did not believe that ‘one generation
can accept responsibility for the acts of earlier generation [sic]’, and he did
so ‘as a matter of principle.’[11] This is
a widely held criticism of the apology, that by apologising, we are effectively
condemning the sons for the sins of their fathers. However, all societies
inherit wealth, resources, and technology amongst other things from previous
generations. It seems reasonable that if I gladly inherit goods which are
derived from immoral actions, such as the mass slaughter and unjust treatment
of indigenous Australians, then it follows that I also inherit the ‘costs’ as
well. Therefore I may still owe a debt of restitution even though I am not
explicitly blameworthy for the immoral actions of previous generations. It also
follows that there are harms that Indigenous Australians could forgive ‘White
Australia’ for, and equally, there are benefits received which ‘White
Australia’ could ask to be forgiven for illegitimately inheriting.
My conclusion follows
the seven claims that were initially mentioned in the introduction: forgiveness
can be a valuable virtue of the citizen and the state if it is balanced
appropriately with other political virtues, and other general virtues such as
truth, respect, and an openness to reconciliation. Political forgiveness may
contain elements of pardon, but for it to be virtuous, political forgiveness must
not be synonymous with pardon or condonation. If it were synonymous with pardon
or condonation, political forgiveness could radically undermine the core values
that we associate with democracy and citizenship. Political forgiveness can
only occur out of a sense of generosity rather than duty. There are times when
it is morally commendable for citizens, states, or political communities to
offer forgiveness. Finally, identity will inevitably be an issue for political
forgiveness, however, there are times when identity is invoked as a reason to
not offer or accept forgiveness when it is simply the atomisation and denial of
responsibility.
Bibliography
Balázs,
Zoltán. “Forgiveness and Repentance.” Public Affairs Quarterly 14, no. 2
(April 1, 2000): 105–127.
Davies,
Anne. “Apology Was a Mistake, Says Feisty Howard.” The Age. Melbourne,
March 12, 2008.
http://www.theage.com.au/articles/2008/03/11/1205125911264.html.
Digeser,
Peter. “Forgiveness and Politics: Dirty Hands and Imperfect Procedures.” Political
Theory 26, no. 5 (October 1, 1998): 700–724.
Downie,
R. S. “Forgiveness.” The Philosophical Quarterly 15, no. 59 (April 1,
1965): 128–134.
Eisikovits,
Nir. “Forget Forgiveness.” Theoria Theoria 51, no. 105 (2004): 31–63.
Mariña,
Jacqueline. “Kant on Grace: A Reply to His Critics.” Religious Studies
33, no. 4 (December 1, 1997): 379–400.
Oxford
English Dictionary. “‘Resentment, N.’.”, n.d.
http://www.oed.com/view/Entry/163487?redirectedFrom=resentment.
Smith,
Roger W. “Redemption and Politics.” Political Science Quarterly 86, no.
2 (June 1, 1971): 205–231.
[1]
Oxford
English Dictionary, “‘Resentment, N.’.”, n.d.,
http://www.oed.com/view/Entry/163487?redirectedFrom=resentment.
[2] Peter Digeser, “Forgiveness and
Politics: Dirty Hands and Imperfect Procedures,” Political Theory 26,
no. 5 (October 1, 1998): 700–724.
[3] Nir Eisikovits, “Forget
Forgiveness,” Theoria Theoria 51, no. 105 (2004): 35.
[4] Generally speaking, abstaining
from forgiveness is no less an active process as the act of forgiving. Neither
can be appropriately viewed as omissions.
[5] R. S. Downie, “Forgiveness,” The
Philosophical Quarterly 15, no. 59 (April 1, 1965): 128.
[6] Zoltán Balázs, “Forgiveness and
Repentance,” Public Affairs Quarterly 14, no. 2 (April 1, 2000): 111.
[7] Downie, “Forgiveness,” 131.
[8] Roger W. Smith, “Redemption and
Politics,” Political Science Quarterly 86, no. 2 (June 1, 1971): 218.
[9] Downie, “Forgiveness,” 131–132.
[10] Jacqueline Mariña, “Kant on
Grace: A Reply to His Critics,” Religious Studies 33, no. 4 (December 1,
1997): 379.
[11] Anne Davies, “Apology Was a
Mistake, Says Feisty Howard,” The Age (Melbourne, March 12, 2008),
http://www.theage.com.au/articles/2008/03/11/1205125911264.html.
No comments:
Post a Comment